Harvard
Magazine gives the text of the motion Professor Danielle Allen offered at
the October 3 FAS meeting:
that the policies of the Harvard
College Handbook for Students for student organizations pertain to
students participating in all student organizations recognized as such by the
Commonwealth of Massachusetts. The Faculty recognizes that on a college campus,
as in society, basic freedoms and rights can come into conflict with each
other. In such situations, the faculty and administration of Harvard College
shall establish policies that protect individual freedoms while upholding the
educational mission of the College.
This must have seemed benign and unobjectionable to the
Faculty Council, since the Council voted in favor, 17-0. (Actually, the wording
of the motion was changed after the Faculty Council voted for it – the revised
version was distributed on paper at the beginning of the FAS meeting. Neither
of these is the draft motion included in the report of the Clark-Khurana
committee. So Professor Allen has offered three versions of her motion so far; perhaps
a fourth will be offered before a vote gets taken. The Faculty Council opposed
my motion, 2-16, so at least one faculty member, and perhaps two, voted for
both.)
What is puzzling is that in a letter
to the Crimson, Professor Allen describes the actual effect her motion would
have.
Its effect would be that students
who join student social groups that have become co-educational and that
otherwise adhere to campus policies for student organizations will not face
repercussions from the administration. Students who join social groups that
have not become co-educational will be ineligible to continue enrollment at the
College.
I have no idea how these conclusions follow from the text of
the motion. The motion gives no protection to membership in any organization,
as my
motion would; it simply suggests which organizations would immediately be subject to institutional control. The
statement that, if Professor Allen’s motion passes, members of noncompliant
student groups would be punished harshly was also made at the FAS meeting and
in an FAQ. As Harvard Magazine reports,
This approach seemingly would have
the virtue of bringing regulation of USGSOs under FAS’s auspices, rather than
relegating the decision to the president (to which some faculty members have
objected, as described above). But it leaves what to do up to the dean. As for
the risks students might face if they do not comply with regular oversight and
regulation, Allen’s FAQ points, briskly, to “suspension or expulsion.”
In the Crimson, Professor Allen describes this way of
proceeding as a “middle way between the two poles of the argument.” Hardly.
There is nothing new in the idea that Harvard should be
trying to get all single-gender clubs to go co-ed; Dean Khurana has been doing
his best at that for the past couple of years, with some success. Professor
Allen’s recourse to Massachusetts Law as justifying such efforts to regulate
the clubs is, as far as I can tell, without teeth. Indeed, it was exactly the
fact that threats from Harvard could not be enforced that led the Clark-Khurana
committee to reject the earlier draft of Professor Allen’s motion. So the
argument that Harvard can legally regulate the clubs doesn’t advance the ball
at all, and leaves the original question: what to do if the clubs do not
cooperate. Professor Allen says their members should be suspended or expelled,
and suggests that her motion implies that, but it doesn’t.
Let’s read it again:
that the policies of the Harvard
College Handbook for Students for student organizations pertain to
students participating in all student organizations recognized as such by the
Commonwealth of Massachusetts.
Yes, of course, the policies of Harvard College apply to
Harvard students—to all Harvard
students. The restrictive clause that follows (students participating in this
or that) adds nothing to what we already know about the applicability of
Harvard rules to Harvard students. The motion does not say that students may
not participate in organizations that do not comply with rules governing
recognized student organizations. That is, of course, the very question my
motion seeks to clarify, by guaranteeing that they may.
-o-
Professor Allen seems to have couched her motion in bland
language so that it will receive broad support, on the understanding that it
would authorize the administration to work out the details without ever
bringing anything contentious to a vote of the full Faculty of Arts and Sciences.
Bland motions are dangerous. Even the unanimously voted FAS statement in favor
of student body diversity has unexpectedly been cited
by the president in justifying her attack on students’ freedom to join outside organizations.
The Allen motion offers a theory to justify Harvard’s legal right
to regulate outside organizations—something I haven’t questioned (though others
may have). So for me, the reference to Massachusetts anti-hazing statutes seems
beside the point. I am not a lawyer, but it seems to me that if Harvard wants
to make a rule that no member of the Bee or the Kappa Kappa Gamma may enroll,
it can. My entire argument is that it shouldn’t
have rules of that kind. In the particular hypothetical Professor Allen
posed, in which a Harvard Pokémon Club staged cheating as an annual club ritual,
she argued that all its members should be expelled. I am all in favor of
throwing out cheaters, but I don’t see why some Pokémon-loving reformer who
refused to go along with the crowd should get tossed too. As I have said many
times, students should be punished for what they do, not for what clubs they
join.
In the course of arguing that even the state sometimes steps
in to regulate private organizations, the assurances in the First Amendment
notwithstanding, Professor Allen makes a curious citation to support her case.
(This and other documents are available here.)
[W]hen the Supreme Court handed
down its 1987 decision in Rotary International, affirming California’s decision
to prohibit gender-exclusive membership policies for clubs of that kind, the
Court argued that “the State’s compelling interests in eliminating
discrimination against women and in assuring them equal access to public
accommodations. . . extends to the acquisition of leadership skills and business
contacts, as well as tangible goods and services” (481 U.S. 537 [1987]:
548-549, emphasis added).
What is odd about that citation is how the Court got to the conclusion
that, in the case of the Rotary Club, it could override the usual protections
of free association. It was because the Rotary Club was so … inclusive. “The evidence in this case
indicates that the relationship among Rotary Club members is not the kind of
intimate or private relation that warrants constitutional protection,” Justice
Powell states in his opinion. As the syllabus summarizes the argument,
In determining whether a particular
association is sufficiently intimate or private to warrant constitutional
protection, consideration must be given to factors such as size, purpose,
selectivity, and whether others are excluded from critical aspects of the
relationship. Here, the relationship among Rotary Club members does not warrant
protection, in light of the potentially large size of local clubs, the high
turnover rate among club members, the inclusive nature of each club's
membership, the public purposes behind clubs' service activities, and the fact
that the clubs encourage the participation of strangers in, and welcome media
coverage of, many of their central activities
To apply this to the final clubs seems to require arguing
simultaneously that Harvard should
regulate them because they are exclusive and can regulate them because they are inclusive! And to the extent
that certain clubs are not particularly selective (some of the sororities, for
example), that makes them more vulnerable to intervention by the authorities,
not less.
I am, in any case, skeptical that Harvard’s interest in
getting women jobs in investment banking has much to do with its insistence
that the Porcellian Club go co-ed. It would be the easiest thing in the world
to ramp up the support of women who wanted high-paying jobs in the financial
sector; the industry would gladly help any Harvard effort to do that. No
Harvard administrator has ever said that anything of the kind was an
institutional priority, except when complaining about the final clubs.
There are other curious aspects to the argument for the
motion, for example the relevance of the anti-hazing statute:
The law has been taken to apply to
final clubs since it was introduced, and the final clubs adhere to its provisions.
Taken by whom? But yes. It’s a criminal statute. I am not
surprised that the clubs acknowledge that they comply with it. It is a huge leap to suggest that this statute
somehow justifies Harvard intervening in their membership practices. And to
take another matter Professor Allen cites, I am also not persuaded that a
Harvard rule against faculty having sex with students—a condition of an
employment relationship—has any relevance to students’ club memberships.
Of course there can be such limits on individual freedoms in
the context of our contractual relationship with the institution. The question
is which ones Harvard should impose. The motion is dangerously vague on that
substantive question, handing it off to “the faculty and administration.” Which
seems to mean that another Clark-Khurana committee will make the rules, and the
Faculty, corporately, will have no say.
I have from the beginning cited the Verba report
and its explicit rejection of the idea of punishing ROTC students for joining what
was then a discriminatory organization. It seems that we can infer how Professor
Allen would want such a dilemma of conflicting freedoms and rights to be
handled in the future. If Harvard is unable to persuade
the government to drop its transgender ban in the military, will we expel our
ROTC cadets?
So what should happen to a motion when its explanatory
materials state a good deal more about its purpose and effects than does its
text? It should be defeated. It is plainly intended as an alternative to my
motion, and if it passes, the administration will surely use the apparatus surrounding
the text to justify its harsh interpretation of the Faculty’s intentions.
-o-
One final point. The motion claims to be moderate because it
limits the scope of institutional reach to student organizations as defined by
Massachusetts Law. So it is meant to swat away the questions about political parties
and the like.
What seems not to have been stated anywhere is that Professor Allen’s Index of Prohibited
Organizations is a great deal longer than that of the Clark-Khurana Committee.
For example, it would include all the ethnic fraternities and sororities. They
were excluded from the Clark-Khurana list because that list was restricted to
organizations that consisted mostly or entirely of Harvard students, and these
organizations (the ones I know about, anyway) are joint with MIT, Tufts, BU, and/or
Wellesley. (Here is a link to
one of them.)
The ethnic fraternities and sororities are a piece of
Harvard culture I don’t know much about. They do not turn up on police blotters
or Ad Board dockets. The only time I ever hear about them is when students tell
me how important their organizations are to them. They are old, some of them; W.E.B.
Dubois was a member of one.
The recent funeral of Dr. Allen Counter, whose name is
synonymous with inclusiveness and diversity at Harvard, ended with a moving
display. About 40 of his fraternity brothers, old and young, including several senior
African-American Harvard faculty and administrators, rose from the
congregation, assembled in the front of the chapel, formed a ring by linking
their little fingers, and gave him a solemn ritual sendoff.
I am not at all sure that Harvard understands the social
structures it is seeking to destroy.
This comment has been removed by a blog administrator.
ReplyDelete